Keyboard Shortcuts?

×
  • Next step
  • Previous step
  • Skip this slide
  • Previous slide
  • mShow slide thumbnails
  • nShow notes
  • hShow handout latex source
  • NShow talk notes latex source

Click here and press the right key for the next slide (or swipe left)

also ...

Press the left key to go backwards (or swipe right)

Press n to toggle whether notes are shown (or add '?notes' to the url before the #)

Press m or double tap to slide thumbnails (menu)

Press ? at any time to show the keyboard shortcuts

\title {Joint Action \\ Lecture 07}
 
\maketitle
 

Lecture 07

Joint Action

\def \ititle {Lecture 07}
\def \isubtitle {Joint Action}
\begin{center}
{\Large
\textbf{\ititle}: \isubtitle
}
 
\iemail %
\end{center}

Question

What distinguishes genuine joint actions from parallel but merely individual actions?

The Simple View

Two or more agents perform an intentional joint action
exactly when there is an act-type, φ, such that
each agent intends that
they, these agents, φ together
and their intentions are appropriately related to their actions.

The Simple View

Two or more agents perform an intentional joint action
exactly when there is an act-type, φ, such that
each agent intends that
they, these agents, φ together
and their intentions are appropriately related to their actions.

Recall our earlier contrast cases ...
***BRATMAN's DIAGNOSIS - have to intend to do it by way of the other’s intentions. This is what is wrong in blocking the aisle shared agency means connecting with each other as agents, not merely as bodies
Bratman’s brilliant idea for avoiding this sort of problem is to suggest that we don’t just each intend the action but rather we each intend to act by way of the other's intentions.
We can put this by saying that our intentions must interlock: mine specify yours and yours mind.
Now this appeal to interlocking intentions enables Bratman to avoid counterexamples like the Tarantino walkers; if I intend that we walk by way of your intention that we walk, I suppose can't rationally also point a gun at you and coerce you to walk.

‘each agent does not just intend that the group perform the […] joint action.

‘Rather, each agent intends as well that the group perform this joint action in accordance with subplans (of the intentions in favor of the joint action) that mesh’

(Bratman 1992: 332)

`each agent does not just intend that the group perform the […] joint action. Rather, each agent intends as well that the group perform this joint action in accordance with subplans (of the intentions in favor of the joint action) that mesh' \citep[p.\ 332]{Bratman:1992mi}.
Our plans are \emph{interconnected} just if facts about your plans feature in mine and conversely.
‘shared intentional [i.e.\ collective] agency consists, at bottom, in interconnected planning agency of the participants’ \citep{Bratman:2011fk}.
In making this idea more precise, Bratman proposes sufficient conditions for us to have a shared intention that we J ... ... the idea is then that an intentional joint action is an action that is appropriately related to a shared intention.

We have a shared intention that we J if

‘1. (a) I intend that we J and (b) you intend that we J

‘2. I intend that we J in accordance with and because of la, lb, and meshing subplans of la and lb; you intend [likewise] …

‘3. 1 and 2 are common knowledge between us’

(Bratman 1993: View 4)

\begin{minipage}{\columnwidth}
\emph{Bratman’s claim}. For you and I to have a collective/shared intention that we J it is sufficient that:
\begin{enumerate}[label=({\arabic*}),itemsep=0pt,topsep=0pt]
\item `(a) I intend that we J and (b) you intend that we J;
\item `I intend that we J in accordance with and because of la, lb, and meshing subplans of la and lb; you intend that we J in accordance with and because of la, lb, and meshing subplans of la and lb;
\item `1 and 2 are common knowledge between us' \citep[View 4]{Bratman:1993je}
\end{enumerate}
\end{minipage}
Note that these conditions are sufficient but not plausibly necessary. If sharing a smile is a joint action, and if human infants in their first year of life are incapable of knowing things about other's knowledge of their intentions about the other's intentions, then to suppose that these conditions were necessary would be to imply that you can't share a smile with an infant.
So the cleanest objection to Bratman will be a counterexample to the sufficiency of his account.
I take this case to be an objection to the idea that we can explain acting as one by appeal to shared intention if we also accept Bratman's claims about what is sufficient for shared intention.

Luke’s objection

  1. Ayesha intends that they J1 in accordance with and because of Ahmed’s intention that they J2
  2. This is tantamount to Ayesha intending that Ahmed’s intention be fulfilled.
  3. Manifestly, they only way for Ahmed’s intention to be fulfilled is if Ayesha and Ahmed J2.

Can Ayesha rationally fail to intend that they, Ayesha and Ahmed, J2?

If not, they meet Bratman’s sufficient conditions for having a shared intention that they J2.

So, at least provisionally, we can add Beatrice & Baldric to the right side of our list of cases of parallel but merely individual action.
This is a case where we have interconnected planning but no shared agency.
I'll strengthen the case for denying that BnB have a shared intention later by constructing a contrasting case in which there really is a shared intention.
(I might mention that there are also mundane counterexamples.)

Joint Action

Parallel but Merely Individual Action

Two people making the cross hit the red square in the ordinary way.

Beatrice & Baldric’s making the cross hit the red square

Two sisters cycling together.

Two strangers cycling the same route side-by-side.

Members of a flash mob simultaneously open their newspapers noisily.

Onlookers simultaneously open their newspapers noisily.

Question

What distinguishes genuine joint actions from parallel but merely individual actions?

So far I have offered objections to (a) The Simple View and (b) Bratman’s account.
We’re still looking for an answer to this question. One possibility (introduced yesterday) is that we can find an answer by considering commitment.
 

Gilbert on Joint Commitment

 
\section{Gilbert on Joint Commitment}
 
\section{Gilbert on Joint Commitment}
Can we give a reductive account of the sort of commitments associated with shared intention? If not, how should we understand it? In particular, is a joint commitment a commitment that two or more people have collectively? And is Gilbert right that joint commitments have contents of a special form?
Here is our basic picture.

Intentions are associated with commitments.

Shared intentions are associated with commitments to each other (contralateral commitments).

Gilbert thinks there is something missing from this picture: joint commitments ...

Gilbert: joint commitment

‘a commitment

by two or more people

of the same two or more people.’

Contrast personal commitment (by me, of me)

Contrast contralateral commitment (by me, of me, to you)

How should we understand the idea that the commitment is ‘by two or more people’? I suggest that this is simply a matter of collective predication.

joint commitment is ‘the collective analogue of a personal commitment’

\citep[p.~85]{gilbert:2014_book}

Gilbert (2013, p. 85)

To explain, recall something we talked about a lot back in lecture 1 ...
Here are two sentences:

The tiny drops fell from the bottle.

- distributive

The tiny drops soaked Zach’s trousers.

- collective

I suggest that the contrast here is clear, and isn’t particular to psychological or normative states.

Their thoughtless actions soaked Zach’s trousers.

- ambiguous (really!)

There are also cases which are ambiguous. (Note that the ambiguity is real; if affects how many times Zach’s trousers must have been soaked for the sentence to be true.) I also want to suggest that the fundamental distinction between personal and joint commitments is of the same kind ...

Ayesha and Beatrice are committed to walking

- also ambiguous (?)

- when collective, it is a joint commitment

So my question was, How should we understand the idea that the commitment is ‘by two or more people’? I’ve suggested that this is simply a matter of collective predication. I should warn you, however, that this isn’t something Gilbert actually says, and it isn’t obvious to me that this must be her view.

Gilbert: joint commitment

‘a commitment

by two or more people

of the same two or more people.’

Contrast personal commitment (by me, of me)

Contrast contralateral commitment (by me, of me, to you)

joint commitment is ‘the collective analogue of a personal commitment’

Gilbert (2013, p. 85)

I’ve been suggesting that

A joint commitment is a commitment we have collectively,

so

a joint commitment is simply a commitment.

Compare: a collective blocking is simply a blocking.
This explains why there may not be very much to say about what joint commitments are, and in particular, why a reductive account may not be needed.

But Gilbert says

joint commitments have

a special kind of content too

and that joint commitments entail contralateral commitments,

which indicates that

a joint commitment is not simply a commitment.

Gilbert: All joint commitments are commitments to emulate, as far as possible, a single body which does something (2013, p. 64).

‘Any joint commitment can be described in a statement of the following form:’ ‘A, B, and so on (or those with property P) are jointly committed as far as is possible (by virtue of their several actions) to emulate a single doer of X’. \citep[p.~311]{gilbert:2014_book}
On emulation: I guess there is a singular version: an actor emulates a single body which believes that $p$, intends to $\phi$, and so on. Likewise, two actors might for some reason share the role (perhaps a young one and an old one). (Here there is not necessarily any joint commitment, but there are commitments with the contents of those which Gilbert specifies as joint commitments.)

‘What is a “single body” [...]? whereas a single human being constitutes a single body [...], a plurality of human individuals does not in and of itself constitute such a body. [...] however, such a plurality can emulate such a body—one with a plurality not only of limbs, eyes, and ears, but also of noses and mouths’

\citep[p.~116]{gilbert:2014_book}

Gilbert (2013, p. 116)

I love the seemingly random ‘not only of limbs, eyes, and ears, but also of noses and mouths’.

‘a “body” here is understood to be a non-collective body.’

‘some of the things we may share an intention to do are designed for two or more participants ... Sally and Tim are jointly committed to intend as a body to produce, by virtue of the actions of each, a single instance of a tennis game with the two of them as participants in that game’ (Gilbert 2013, p. 117)

Why does Gilbert insist on the form? I don’t think it adds anything to our understanding of joint commitment as such. But it is essential to Gilbert’s use of joint commitment to analyse social phenomena.
So Gilbert’s analysis of joint commitment actually has two parts.

Gilbert on joint commitment

[1] The subject:

‘a commitment

by two or more people

of the same two or more people.’

[2] The content:

All joint commitments are commitments to emulate, as far as possible, a single body which does something (2013, p. 64).

To repeat, I’ve been suggesting that

A joint commitment is a commitment we have collectively,

so

a joint commitment is simply a commitment.

Compare: a collective blocking is simply a blocking.
This explains why there may not be very much to say about what joint commitments are, and in particular, why a reductive account may not be needed.

But Gilbert says

joint commitments have a special kind of content too

and that joint commitments entail contralateral commitments,

which indicates that

a joint commitment is not simply a commitment.

commitment:

personal

contralateral

collective (?)

shared (?)

sense of (?)

How closely should we follow Gilbert in thinking about commitment? I suspect we will eventually need all of these to understand shared agency. As far as I know, Gilbert is the leading authority in this area. And her position is largely untenable. I know that some relatively new people are moving into this area in a big way (especially John Michael), so I expect to see some major developments. And this is asking a lot, I know, but maybe you can contribute in your own work.
 

Distributive / Collective / Shared

 
\section{Distributive / Collective / Shared}
 
\section{Distributive / Collective / Shared}
Can we make sense of a three-fold contrast between distributive, collective and shared (/joint).

distributive

vs

collective commitment (or intention)

vs

shared (or joint) intention (or commitment)

Ayesha and Beatrice played the horse in our pantomime.

Case 1-individual: actors who perform a role distributively (different theatres, each performs the role) vs Case 1-collective: actors who perform a role collectively (one plays the back of the horse, the other plays the front of the horse)
Case 1-individual: actors who perform a role distributively (different theatres, each performs the role)
vs
Case 1-shared: actors who share a role: one plays the character as a child, the other plays the character as an adult. (Compare Bratman on shared intention: Bratman)
Case 1-collective: actors who perform a role collectively (one plays the back of the horse, the other plays the front of the horse) vs Case 1-shared: actors who share a role: one plays the character as a child, the other plays the character as an adult.
Could give blame as a second example.
You have two minutes to think of another three-way contrast.
Think of Bratman on shared intention. According to Bratman, a shared intention is something that we share in the same sense that Ayesha and Beatrice share the role of pantomime horse when one plays the young horse and the other the old horse. The shared intention comprises intentions and knowledge states some of which are mine and some of which are yours.
By contrast, a collective commitment or intention would be one that we collectively have. It’s analogous to the case where Ayesha and Beatrice join their bodies to play the horse. (That is, we would be its plural subject.)
What Gilbert has in mind is not a shared commitment, where the bits are distributed across people, but ...
... a collective commitment, something that is yours and mine, so that we are the plural subjects of that commitment.
Logically, you can see that there are these alternative possibilities. We will explore the idea of collective mental states (plural subjects) later.

conclusion

In conclusion, ...
  • Gilbert offers an account of joint commitment.
  • There are some questions about how to interpret her account.
  • Gilbert differs from Bratman in two ways: (i) commitment; (ii) collective (vs shared).